Showing posts with label Maths. Show all posts
Showing posts with label Maths. Show all posts

Thursday, January 23, 2025

Freedom

is the freedom to say that 2 + 2 is

no more nor less than the number of ones in (1 + 1) + (1 + 1)

How could that be what freedom is? Who would deny that that is what 2 + 2 is? And how would their denying it get in the way of our being free?

Surprisingly, it is the experts on numbers who deny it. A hundred years ago, academic mathematicians redefined all of their terminology in order to lose some puzzling arithmetic in that translation. Why was that arithmetic too puzzling for them?

That arithmetic makes sense if we assume that there is a God who is able to change in some rather transcendental ways (a God who is more like the Trinity than a thing, and who may well be above and beyond time and changes of ordinary kinds), but it is very hard to see how it could make sense in any other way. And scientific academia was increasingly atheistic in the twentieth century.

Insofar as that arithmetic only makes sense if there is such a God, it proves that there is such a God. And the truth will set you free. But that proof was hidden by that translation. And by related redefinitions of words like truth and proof, as described here:

Freedom

That link opens a Google Doc (8,733 words, 28 pages) in a new window.

Friday, November 08, 2024

On the Hiddenness of God

I emailed The Hiddenness of God to thousands of mathematicians, to see if any were interested in the proof buried beneath the foundations of their subject, and I have had some replies already. The following conversation has been edited, but it is fairly typical, in case you were wondering what mathematicians would make of my proof.

Mathematician: Russell's paradox (and Epimenides' before him) demonstrates simply that the concept of "truth value" that many logicians had assumed to be well-defined on all statements, and which works well most of the time, must in fact have a few limitations. When we talk about truth values too loosely, plain English hides the fact that we're discussing a function from the class of propositions to the set {T,F} that may not in fact be wholly defined. It's no more mysterious than the discovery that division by 0 can't be defined except by giving up several arithmetic properties that are otherwise unproblematic. Russell simply shows a similar restriction for truth values of self-referential statements. This is well-understood. And Cantor's theorem isn't even a paradox: it just shows that if we define an ordering by "size" on infinite sets, then the rationals and the reals are in different size classes - and why shouldn't they be? Our ability to "comprehend" either is ill-defined (this is where plain English lets us down): we do not know everything even about large finite numbers (which digit appears most often in 9^(9^(9^(9^(9^9)))) ?) and we know a very great deal about the real numbers, more numerous than the natural numbers though they are.

Me: While Russell's paradox did do that, the heap paradox and the liar paradox had done it thousands of years earlier. And while Cantor's theorem is indeed not a paradox, it exists within axiomatic set theory. Cantor's paradox arises for the numbers that Cantor was working with, which were essentially the same as the numbers that we learn about at school. And there is an obvious and unambiguous meaning to the word "two," for example: two is the number of things in any collection that has as many things in it as the sum 1 + 1 has units in it (where the sense of "as many things" is equinumerosity).

Mathematician: I think the heap paradox is most easily interpreted as showing the axiom that one grain less than a heap is still a heap to be inconsistent. Heapiness is problematic in other ways as well. If we base our definition on general opinion, we more or less have to test it by asking an observer "is this a heap?" and the answer may depend on the observer. If we don't appeal to opinion, there's no reason not to define a heap as a thousand grains or more of sand, or sand grains piled at least five deep. And while what you said is true for "two" there are more real numbers (in the usual sense) than there are definitions in finite strings of characters... and this happens precisely at the spot we're interested in.

Me: Plain English is good enough for the definition of "two," though; and similarly, for an arbitrary counting number (even though most counting numbers are too big for us to imagine anything about them other than that they are counting numbers). And Cantor's paradox arises for arbitrary subcollections of subcollections of [...] subcollections of counting numbers. The real numbers are complicated (and Richard's paradox is interesting) but irrelevant to Cantor's paradox. As for the answer to "is this a heap?" I think that it can depend on the observer, and that that is one of the reasons why some piles of sand are only heaps as much as they are not heaps. Insofar as they are heaps, removing a single grain of sand would make a negligible difference to that. And for such a pile, "that pile is a heap" would be true only as much as it was not true. And similarly, the liar paradox shows that there are self-referential statements that are true only as much as they are not true. So, Russell's paradox is more like the liar paradox (and the heap paradox) than Cantor's paradox.

Mathematician: I think the heap paradox is somewhat different in that it can be dealt with by saying that "well, it seems that we need to sharpen our definition of a heap. A heap will be any collection of sand numbering more than ten grains, stable, and at least a quarter as tall as it is high." That's roughly what Cantor did with infinities... a fairly small patch on existing math. The first was a paradox, and not the second, only because people had more preconceptions about heaps. Cantor's result is more a proof by contradiction, eliminating a wring turning in an exploration of new territory. If Eubulides of Miletus had been researching novel ways to store sand (insight - we don't need a bucket!) he might have used the sorites paradox similarly. The liar paradox can't really be explained away by inventing a better liar: it needs the concept of truth that underlies all philosophy to be redefined. Similarly, Russell's paradox involved a complete revamping of basic set theory.

Me: I don't think that the heap paradox can be dealt with by saying that we need to sharpen the definition of "heap" because similar paradoxes occur with almost all of our words (as Russell observed) and because our words simply have the meanings that they have: if we redefine what "truth" means, then we are no longer talking about the truth of our words. I suppose that Cantor's paradox is the proof by contradiction that you think it is if there is no God, but is the proof by contradiction that I think it is (a proof that there is a God) if we should not redefine what "truth" means in order to avoid an inconvenient proof.

Mathematician: It's true that if we take "Cantor's paradox" as a standalone result, rather than as the obvious (in retrospect) conclusion of his construction of sets of demonstrably different cardinality, it looks more like Russell's paradox. That's not the angle I'm used to seeing it from, but I think I see your point. Nonetheless, in Cantor's case we don't have to redefine "truth", we merely have to redefine "set" so that some things we would have naively called sets are "classes" with a smaller set of permitted construction rules. As for the relevance to God: I am not a believer, but quite happy to argue hypotheticals. I agree with Aquinas that any god that exists must be bound by the laws of logic. These are the same laws of logic that bind us: and I see no reason why using a definition of "set" that Cantor showed to be inconsistent could be a divine attribute, let alone why we should want it to be so. Aquinas says in effect that, regarding logic, what's good enough for Cantor (if Cantor is right) is good enough for God. You don't get around Cantor by supposing "theological unions" of sets that somehow differ from those of set theory (or, if you do, you must explain their properties fully and equiconsistently with ZFC or some other well-defined system).

Me: I agree that we should be bound by the laws of logic, and I take that to mean that we cannot just make those laws up. And I am certainly not trying to get around Cantor by supposing theological unions (whatever they are). I am questioning his assumption that mathematical collections must exist timelessly. Cantor chose to believe in the existence of collections that were inconsistent, rather than give up that assumption! Mathematicians can of course use any definition of “set” and “class” that they like, but there is still the paradoxical behaviour of mathematical collections (in the logical sense) to explain. Cantor’s paradox showed that his conception of set was inconsistent, but his conception included the assumption that mathematical collections exist (insofar as such things can be said to exist) timelessly. Incidentally, although Russell found his paradox while he was thinking about Cantor’s paradox, I don’t think that Cantor’s paradox is like Russell’s paradox.

Mathematician: My view is that the word "exist" is not used in mathematics in the sense that Mount Everest is and Alma Cogan isn’t (as the guy on the Monty Python record put it). It's an axiomatically-defined predicate in mathematical theories and metatheories (parallel lines exist in the Euclidean plane, they do not exist in the projective plane). From this viewpoint, I don't see time/timelessness as having anything to do with mathematical existence (I suppose one could take a time-dependent Platonist view where pi really was three in Old Testament times, but that is not how I see it).

Me: For most mathematicians nowadays, mathematical existence is indeed existence within an axiomatic structure, and for such structures it is consistency that matters. And within set theory, there is only Cantor’s theorem. But for numbers like the counting numbers and the number of all the counting numbers, and so on, it is logic that matters: such numbers are essentially properties of logically possible collections (you and I are two people, and we would have been two possible people had we never existed, and the properties of that “two” are logically prior to any axiomatic model of them). And if it is logically possible for there to be a God, then there are all the numbers (in that sense) that give rise to Cantor’s paradox. That is how I have been able to show that if it is logically possible for there to be a God then there is a God, because it is only if there is a God that such numbers could possibly be getting more numerous (and it is only in the last hundred years that mathematicians would have denied that such numbers were part of mathematics).

Mathematician: The statement that "numbers are getting more numerous" is, if not downright false, highly ambiguous. Our mathematical knowledge may encompass more numbers, but a given axiom system implies the same numbers yesterday, today, and forever, even if nobody alive at some time understands that. Furthermore I hold, with (for instance) Aquinas, that it is a logical necessity that no deity could change; so, claiming that the creation of new numbers within a fixed axiom system implies the existence of a god is true only ex falsi quodlibet. Apart from that major objection, if your argument did prove the existence of some entity X, I think (again, hypothetically) that it would fall far short of showing that this X was what was generally called "a god," let alone a specific faith's God.

Me: The numbers in “numbers are getting more numerous” do not exist within any axiom system, but as a consequence of there being numbers of things in the world (such as us two). Axiomatic models of them are timeless, but they themselves are properties of logically possible collections of things, so it is a matter of objective fact whether they are timeless or not. And while we naturally assume that they (and logical possibilities generally) are timeless, it is conceivable that they (and some other logical possibilities) are not timeless if there is a God who is not timeless. As for your belief that if there was a God then that God would have to be above and beyond time and change, I suppose that you have a good reason for believing that, but as I do not know what that reason is, I cannot say why it is not a valid reason (and similarly for your reason for believing that X could not be called a God, unless it is the same reason). I have thought a lot about the reasons that are in the literature, and none of them are valid when it comes to the God that Cantor’s paradox shows exists (which did not surprise me because a lot of the religious believers who take God to be above and beyond time and change would also say that He is above and beyond our logical abilities).

Mathematician: You would seem to be saying that there's an argument showing, on the basis of some axiom system, that some number (call it Stigma) exists... and that at some time in the past the same argument was not valid, or was valid but did not show that Stigma existed. A fun science-fiction idea, but in reality if we pick at it, expanding the argument out to a long but finite list of axiomatic steps and going through it a step at a time, there's a step that somehow didn't work then and does now. But that step is supposedly an instance of an axiom, so the axiom set has changed. Gods whose powers vary in time (depending on who's stolen whose hammer today) are more at home in comic books than in philosophical arguments; when I said "god" I meant the sort of god that modern philosophy usually considers, whose view of the universe is in some sense ultimate and synonymous with reality. If the power of such a god were greater today than yesterday, it would have to have been less than it might have been yesterday. Which, as Spinoza would have said, is absurd.

Me: I too meant the God whose view of the universe is the universe. And I agree that the power of such a God cannot increase, or decrease. However, the knowledge of such a creator would increase as a matter of logical necessity whenever any particular thing was created (as I show in the first “chapter” of my first email). As for your interpretation of what I was saying in terms of an axiom system, the existence of the most basic numbers (1, 2, 3 etc.) does not have to be existence within any axiomatic system, even if there is a God. The existence of such numbers could be the logical possibility of there being collections of that many things (which is why my argument is a logical argument based on Cantor’s original paradox). Etc.

Monday, July 08, 2024

A mathematical poem

1 + 2 = 3

0 + 12 = 3 × 4

12 = 3 × 4
56 = 7 × 8

0 + 12 = 3 × 4
5 + 67 = 8 × 9

Sunday, January 01, 2023

🥳The number 23

1 + 23 = 4 × (5 – 6 + 7)
1 = 23 – 4 – 5 – 6 – 7

Furthermore, 23 is two less than 25 (which is a square number)
and in two years time it will be 2025 (another square number).

Interestingly, 2025 = (20 + 25) × (20 + 25)

Sunday, January 02, 2022

Sets

Sets
(two thousand words) will be
section 2 of chapter 2 of my book:
The Way of Things

Saturday, January 01, 2022

Authorial Authority

Authorial Authority
(two and a half thousand words) will be
section 2 of chapter 4 of my book:
The Way of Things

Friday, December 10, 2021

Truth

Truth
(three thousand words) will be
section 3 of chapter 5 of my book:
The Way of Things

Monday, December 06, 2021

Russell's Paradoxes

Russell's Paradoxes
(two and a half thousand words) will be
section 2 of chapter 5 of my book:
The Way of Things

Sunday, December 05, 2021

Heaps

Heaps
(two and a half thousand words) will be
section 1 of chapter 5 of my book:
The Way of Things

Wednesday, December 01, 2021

The Shape of Time

The Shape of Time
(two thousand words) will be
section 1 of chapter 4 of my book:
The Way of Things

Friday, November 12, 2021

Impossibly Many Things

Impossibly Many Things
(one thousand words) will be
section 2 of chapter 3 of my book:
The Way of Things

Many Things

Many Things
(two thousand words) will be
section 1 of chapter 3 of my book:
The Way of Things

Monday, November 08, 2021

Explanations

Explanations
(five and a half thousand words) will be
section 4 of chapter 2 of my book:
The Way of Things

Thursday, October 14, 2021

Proofs

Proofs
(five and a half thousand words) will be
section 3 of chapter 2 of my book:
The Way of Things

Sunday, October 03, 2021

Infinities

Infinities
(two thousand words) will be
section 1 of chapter 2 of my book:
The Way of Things

Thursday, September 23, 2021

Low Expectations

Low Expectations
(five and a half thousand words) will be
section 2 of chapter 1 of my book:
The Way of Things

Tuesday, August 31, 2021

The Lie of the Land

The Lie of the Land
(two thousand words) will be
section 1 of chapter 1 of my book:
The Way of Things

Monday, July 12, 2021

First stab at a Book!

Here is a rather messy google doc: The Way of Things (it is over a hundred thousand words; I am going to tidy it up and post it section by section as I rewrite it :-)

Thursday, November 19, 2020

A True Contradiction?

(a) the maths

Since adding zero to any amount does not change it, we can keep adding zeroes forever, and it will make no difference. Such additions always amount to adding zero.

We might write that as 0 = 0 + 0 + 0 + 0 + 0 + …, which can be spread out like this:

       0      =                             0                            +                             0                           +             . . .

Each 0 on the right-hand side can be replaced by 1 – 1, to give:

       0      =             (1                         1)            +             (1                         1)            +             . . .

In the next equation, the brackets have been removed.

       0      =             1                           1              +             1                           1            +             . . .

In the next equation, brackets have been put back in, in different places.

       0      =             1              +             (–1         +             1)            +             (–1         +             . . .

We now replace each (–1 + 1) with 0.

       0      =             1              +                             0                              +                         0              . . .

All those zeroes on the right-hand side add up to zero, of course. But that means that:

       0      =             1

Clearly 0 = 1 is false. So, where did we go wrong? Well, since the last equation was false, the equation above it must also have been false (the only difference between those two equations is the first equation, which was clearly true). And the next one, going upwards, 0 = 1 + (–1 + 1) + (–1 + 1) + ..., must have been false too, as each of those “(–1 + 1)” does equal zero.

Going the other way, from the first equation, 0 = 0 + 0 + ..., which was clearly true, the next equation, 0 = (1 – 1) + (1 – 1) + ..., is similarly true, because each of those “(1 – 1)” is zero.

In between those two equations, one false and one true, we have the infinite sum 1 – 1 + 1 – 1 + …, which was originally described by the Italian theologian and mathematician Guido Grandi (1671–1742).

Grandi was interested in the calculus (as described by Leibniz). And in the calculus, an infinite sum is equal to the limit of the initial finite sums as their length tends to infinity. Grandi’s infinite sum 1 – 1 + 1 – 1 + ... has initial sums that alternate between 1 and 0 = 1 – 1 endlessly (the next are 1 = 1 – 1 + 1 and 0 = 1 – 1 + 1 – 1). Since the initial sums tend to no limit, Grandi’s infinite sum is not given any value by the calculus.

By removing the brackets, we moved from an infinite sum of zeroes, which is equal to zero, to Grandi’s infinite sum, which has no value. Adding brackets differently then took us from Grandi’s infinite sum to a sum that is one plus an infinite number of zeroes, which is equal to one.

(b) the physics

You may be familiar with the idea of a particle/antiparticle pair appearing out of the vacuum. Such pairs give rise to Hawking radiation from a black hole, but all we need to know here is that such pairs can, in theory, appear from the background fields of the vacuum. Once formed, the particle and antiparticle are moving away from their point of origin, so we might picture them moving downwards, like this: /\ (near a black hole, one of them might be swallowed by the black hole, while the other flies away from the black hole, giving rise to Hawking radiation).

Space does not seem to be infinite, but an infinite space is a physical possibility. And in such a space, an endless line of such particles/antiparticle pairs is a possibility, for all that it is highly unlikely. We might picture them like this: /\/\/\/\/\... (the zig-zag continues to spatial infinity).

The top of that zig-zag pictures a line of particle/antiparticle pairs appearing, which might be modelled mathematically by modelling each particle as +1 and each antiparticle as –1. We then get this equation:

0 = (1 – 1) + (1 – 1) + (1 – 1) + (1 – 1) + (1 – 1) + ...

Each (1 – 1) represents a particle/antiparticle pair appearing.

They move downwards in such a way that each antiparticle collides with the particle from the pair to the right, so that they are both annihilated. The particle at the extreme left of the zig-zag is not annihilated. The bottom of the zig-zag therefore pictures events that are modelled rather well by this equation:

1 = 1 + (–1 + 1) + (–1 + 1) + (–1 + 1) + (–1 + 1) + (–1 + ...

Each (–1 + 1) corresponds to an antiparticle and a particle annihilating each other.

In between those two equations, there is no mathematical sum, neither 0 nor 1. That corresponds to infinitely many particles and antiparticles just being there, in between their creation and their almost total annihilation. The highly improbable, but physically possible, appearance of this particle from an infinite vacuum is therefore so well-modelled by 0 = 1 – 1 + 1 – 1 + ... = 1, that it is essentially an instance of it. It is in a very similar way that Jack and Jill being a couple is an instance of 1 + 1 = 2.

Such equations as 1 + 1 = 2 only exist because they are such good descriptions of any collection of two things. It is the physical instantiation that ultimately justifies the mathematical equation. And of course, to say of what is, that it is, is to say something that is true. Which raises the following question.

(c) the questions

Could 0 = 1 – 1 + 1 – 1 + ... = 1 be a true contradiction?

In order to think about that question logically, should we use paraconsistent logic?

(d) my answers

Although a contradiction can be used as a description that is such a good description, it should count as a true description, that does not mean that the contradiction is true. Consider how there are two ways in which 1 + 1 = 2 is true. It is true as a description of Jack and Jill, and it is, in a different way, true by definition (of 2). Contradictions are false (as a rule). And it is not at all contradictory for there to be no particle and then, at a later time, one particle.

In order to answer that question correctly, I needed to think logically. Why would anyone think that a mathematical model of reasoning that is not a very good model of logical reasoning would help?