Monday, August 01, 2022
Sunday, February 21, 2021
What is it like to be a bat?
You know what it is like to be a bat. To be a bat is to be a mammal like no other. You spend half the day dozing in caves, and then you all leave together. You flap about, in order to get anywhere. You find out where you are by seeing how the sounds you make come back to you. You are where all the others are. Each of you is there because everyone else is there. Everyone else is a bit batty. You know what it is like to be a bat.
Tuesday, February 16, 2021
Health and Safety
"Police officers are, quite rightly, furious at the government for failing to prioritise them in the vaccination schedule."
Click on that quote for more on that "quite rightly,"
Blaming the government is how our democracy works; but I was wondering, who failed to get the police vaccinated in the early days of this pandemic, when it would have done them (and therefore us) much more good?
Many months ago (here is a link to one timeline) the vaccines were safe enough to be given to thousands of volunteers, for phases II and III of the testing process (for a description of those phases see the quote below, which is cut-and-pasted from WHO). Could some of the vaccines not have been made available then, for key workers who volunteered (for the vaccines, not for participation in the trials, which were presumably randomized)? Tinkering with the timetable of the current roll-out of mass vaccinations would inevitably involve some risk to that roll-out. Why do people who failed to think this through earlier, when it would have done more good, now think that they know better than the government how to balance those risks?
Here is that WHO quote:
"An experimental vaccine is first tested in animals to evaluate its safety and potential to prevent disease. It is then tested in human clinical trials, in three phases:
In phase I, the vaccine is given to a small number of volunteers to assess its safety, confirm it generates an immune response, and determine the right dosage.
In phase II, the vaccine is usually given [to] hundreds of volunteers, who are closely monitored for any side effects, to further assess its ability to generate an immune response. In this phase, data are also collected whenever possible on disease outcomes, but usually not in large enough numbers to have a clear picture of the effect of the vaccine on disease. Participants in this phase have the same characteristics (such as age and sex) as the people for whom the vaccine is intended. In this phase, some volunteers receive the vaccine and others do not, which allows comparisons to be made and conclusions drawn about the vaccine.
In phase III, the vaccine is given to thousands of volunteers – some of whom receive the investigational vaccine, and some of whom do not, just like in phase II trials. Data from both groups is carefully compared to see if the vaccine is safe and effective against the disease it is designed to protect against."
Thursday, November 19, 2020
A True Contradiction?
(a) the maths
Since adding zero to any amount does not change it, we can keep adding zeroes forever, and it will make no difference. Such additions always amount to adding zero.
We might write that as 0 = 0 + 0 + 0 + 0 + 0 + …, which can be spread out like this:
0 = 0 + 0 + .
. .
Each 0 on the right-hand side can be replaced by 1 – 1, to give:
0 = (1 – 1) + (1 – 1) + . . .
In the next equation, the brackets
have been removed.
0 = 1 – 1 + 1 – 1 + . . .
In the next equation, brackets have
been put back in, in different places.
0 = 1 + (–1 + 1) + (–1 + . . .
We now replace each (–1 + 1) with
0.
0 = 1 + 0 + 0 .
. .
All those zeroes on the right-hand
side add up to zero, of course. But that means that:
0 = 1
Clearly 0 = 1 is false. So, where did we go wrong? Well, since the last equation was false, the equation above it must also have been false (the only difference between those two equations is the first equation, which was clearly true). And the next one, going upwards, 0 = 1 + (–1 + 1) + (–1 + 1) + ..., must have been false too, as each of those “(–1 + 1)” does equal zero.
Going the other way, from the first equation, 0 = 0 + 0 + ..., which was clearly true, the next equation, 0 = (1 – 1) + (1 – 1) + ..., is similarly true, because each of those “(1 – 1)” is zero.
In between those two equations, one false and one true, we have the infinite sum 1 – 1 + 1 – 1 + …, which was originally described by the Italian theologian and mathematician Guido Grandi (1671–1742).
Grandi was interested in the calculus (as described by Leibniz). And in the calculus, an infinite sum is equal to the limit of the initial finite sums as their length tends to infinity. Grandi’s infinite sum 1 – 1 + 1 – 1 + ... has initial sums that alternate between 1 and 0 = 1 – 1 endlessly (the next are 1 = 1 – 1 + 1 and 0 = 1 – 1 + 1 – 1). Since the initial sums tend to no limit, Grandi’s infinite sum is not given any value by the calculus.
By removing the brackets, we moved from an infinite sum of zeroes, which is equal to zero, to Grandi’s infinite sum, which has no value. Adding brackets differently then took us from Grandi’s infinite sum to a sum that is one plus an infinite number of zeroes, which is equal to one.
(b) the physics
You may be familiar with the idea of a particle/antiparticle pair appearing out of the vacuum. Such pairs give rise to Hawking radiation from a black hole, but all we need to know here is that such pairs can, in theory, appear from the background fields of the vacuum. Once formed, the particle and antiparticle are moving away from their point of origin, so we might picture them moving downwards, like this: /\ (near a black hole, one of them might be swallowed by the black hole, while the other flies away from the black hole, giving rise to Hawking radiation).
Space does not seem to be infinite, but an infinite space is a physical possibility. And in such a space, an endless line of such particles/antiparticle pairs is a possibility, for all that it is highly unlikely. We might picture them like this: /\/\/\/\/\... (the zig-zag continues to spatial infinity).
The top of that zig-zag pictures a line of particle/antiparticle pairs appearing, which might be modelled mathematically by modelling each particle as +1 and each antiparticle as –1. We then get this equation:
0 = (1 – 1) + (1 – 1) + (1 – 1) +
(1 – 1) + (1 – 1) + ...
Each (1 – 1) represents a particle/antiparticle pair appearing.
They move downwards in such a way that each antiparticle collides with the particle from the pair to the right, so that they are both annihilated. The particle at the extreme left of the zig-zag is not annihilated. The bottom of the zig-zag therefore pictures events that are modelled rather well by this equation:
1 = 1 + (–1 + 1) + (–1 + 1) + (–1 +
1) + (–1 + 1) + (–1 + ...
Each (–1 + 1) corresponds to an antiparticle and a particle annihilating each other.
In between those two equations, there is no mathematical sum, neither 0 nor 1. That corresponds to infinitely many particles and antiparticles just being there, in between their creation and their almost total annihilation. The highly improbable, but physically possible, appearance of this particle from an infinite vacuum is therefore so well-modelled by 0 = 1 – 1 + 1 – 1 + ... = 1, that it is essentially an instance of it. It is in a very similar way that Jack and Jill being a couple is an instance of 1 + 1 = 2.
Such equations as 1 + 1 = 2 only exist because they are such good descriptions of any collection of two things. It is the physical instantiation that ultimately justifies the mathematical equation. And of course, to say of what is, that it is, is to say something that is true. Which raises the following question.
(c) the questions
Could 0 = 1 – 1 + 1 – 1 + ... = 1 be a true contradiction?
In order to think about that question logically, should we use paraconsistent logic?
(d) my answers
Although a contradiction can be used as a description that is such a good description, it should count as a true description, that does not mean that the contradiction is true. Consider how there are two ways in which 1 + 1 = 2 is true. It is true as a description of Jack and Jill, and it is, in a different way, true by definition (of 2). Contradictions are false (as a rule). And it is not at all contradictory for there to be no particle and then, at a later time, one particle.
In order to answer that question correctly, I needed to think logically. Why would anyone think that a mathematical model of reasoning that is not a very good model of logical reasoning would help?
Monday, January 27, 2020
Murder in the Academy
Ducks are not as daft as they look. Not by comparison with philosophers. To see how daft philosophers are, you only have to consider the Trolley Problem. Here are four versions of it, called Transplant, Footbridge, Lever and Tiger.
In each version, a scenario is described. You are told what will definitely happen if you choose to do something (someone will die), and what will definitely happen if you do not choose to do it (three people will die). You have to decide what you should do.
One of your friends is a doctor, and three of her patients will die within the week if they do not get transplants. One needs a heart, and the others each need a lung and a kidney. And it is not that they will probably die. They will definitely die.
You also know Mr E, whose organs are perfectly compatible with those three patients. If they had those organs, all three would go on to live long, happy and productive lives. As it is, not only are they dying within the week, Mr E does not have much to look forward to either. He works in a zoo but he does not like animals.
The question is: should you kill Mr E? If you do, you will be able to deliver the corpse to your friend the doctor, who will be able to operate successfully on her three patients. You will commit a perfect murder, and have a fake organ donor form to give to your doctor friend along with the body. You will be able to walk away with no untoward repercussions.
The answer is: No. Murder is wrong, and you should not do it. There is nothing complicated about this scenario. Almost everyone who hears this version of the problem agrees that the answer is "No." I suppose that it could be argued that, because killing in self-defense is allowed, you should be allowed to kill an innocent person in order to save three lives. But that would be daft. And you would think that a philosopher would know why. But the following version of the problem seems to confuse them.
You are on a footbridge over a bend in a railway track. Three people are working on the track on one side of the bridge. They cannot hear an approaching train over the noise of their equipment. From where you are you can see it coming from the other direction. It will pass under the bridge and then hit those three workers, who have their backs to you. It will not be able to stop in time. It will kill all three.
There is also a fat man, Mr E, sitting on the edge of the bridge, eating some sandwiches and thinking about going back to work. You happen to know that if you pushed him off, he would land on the track in front of the train and slow it enough for it to stop without killing any of the workers, although he would die instead. Again, no one would have to know what you had done. You could push him off, to save three workers, and be on your way with no one any the wiser. Should you push Mr E off?
It would of course still be wrong to murder Mr E. Imagine if you did not know that! And yet a lot of philosophers think that you should push the fat man off the footbridge. It is not that they think that murder is alright. It is that they do not realise that that is what the question is asking. That is because these problems are usually presented in the opposite order: Lever first, then Footbridge.
3) Lever
This is a lot like Footbridge. The only difference is that instead of a bridge there is a side track, onto which the oncoming train could be diverted. The train would go straight on, onto the side track, instead of going round the bend in the track, towards the workers.
You are standing by the bend, where there is a lever that controls where the train will go. You can see the workers in one direction, and the train that they cannot see (or hear) in the other. In this version, Mr E is sitting on one of the rails of the side track, eating his sandwiches and listening to some music. He is too far away for you to pull the lever, diverting the train onto the side track, and then run to him in time to warn him. And the workers are also too far away for you to warn them. So, three people will die, or just one. Should you pull the lever killing Mr E?
This is so similar to the other versions, it should be obvious that the answer is again "No." Otherwise you would be killing one person, instead of killing no one. You would not be choosing the lesser of two evils (one person dead instead of three), you would be choosing the greater of two evils: murdering someone instead of watching three people get killed by a train (while you try and fail to think of some other way of helping, presumably).
A lot of philosophers think that the answer in this case is "Yes." When people consider Lever, it seems that they naturally see it as the question "should three people die, or just one?" They tend to think that it is akin to allocating resources. Or perhaps they think that the lever should have been manned by someone who should choose to save the most lives (much as Churchill was not wrong to order the bombing of Dresden), and that they would simply be filling in for that absent person.
Some philosophers do notice that those two versions are significantly different. But then they tend to imagine that they have some evidence for a half-baked "philosophical" explanation of why they are different. Not many of them go back, from Footbridge, to revise their answer to this version; and of course, they should do that, because these two versions are not actually that different. My final version emphasizes their similarities.
By way of introducing it, consider how pushing Mr E in front of a train is a bit like pushing him in front of a tiger. If you lifted Mr E up on a platform, and then dropped him in front of the tiger, it would be like Footbridge. Would it make much of a difference if you lowered him, so that the tiger had to jump down onto him, a bit like Lever?
In this version, a tiger is rushing down a tunnel towards three children. It will kill them if it reaches them. However, there is a pit between the tiger and the children, currently covered over with a board. If the board is removed, then the tiger will fall into the pit and the children will be saved. You can remove the board in time to save them. However, it was Mr E who dug that pit, and he is still in there, hiding from the tiger. If you remove the board then he will definitely be killed by it. Should you remove the board?
I would be tempted to. I could always say that I did not know that Mr E was in the pit; and I would not just be watching three children being savaged by a tiger. So, this version is a lot like Lever. Still, even a murder that I feel to be justified is still a murder. One explanation of why Footbridge is different to Lever, given by several philosophers, is that in Footbridge you are primarily killing a man, only incidentally saving some others, whereas in Lever you are primarily saving some men, only incidentally killing another.
The failure of so many of philosophers to understand such simple scenarios is not an insignificant failing. Philosophers claim to be our experts when it comes to thinking logically: many of them teach Logic. Some of them, following Kant, think that it is wrong to use someone as a means to an end. That is, it is wrong to use Mr E as a brake (or to use him as big-cat-food), although it is alright if he is in the way of a diverted train (or if he happens to be in the pit you are dropping the tiger into). And it is true that in Tiger you are diverting the tiger onto Mr E, not putting Mr E in front of the tiger. But surely it is daft to think that it matters much which one falls toward the other.
If you throw a spear at someone (or pull the trigger on a gun, or a lever to divert a train) and kill her, how are you murdering her less than if you deliberately push her onto a spike? Relatively less daft is what I took a break from philosophy to spend more time looking at: ducks, on the village duck-pond. In this photo, a pair were busy making ducklings. They seemed to know what they were doing (although as it happens, the male's penis is like a corkscrew, and the female's vagina coils the other way).
Monday, September 02, 2019
What if there is a proof?
If there is a perfectly logical proof that there is a God, the experts would take themselves to be knowing that there is probably no such thing and not waste their valuable time checking the logic of that purported proof. But perhaps it would be different elsewhere. Perhaps it would have been different.
If Cantor's paradox is essentially a proof that there is a God, then anyone who could have noticed Cantor's generalised diagonal argument could have discovered that proof. Could it have been discovered by the mathematicians of the ancient world? Might that have been part of the significance of Amun-Ra, or Jehovah, or Plato's Form of Forms? It is too late to know now (although the experts would say that they know what is probably the case).
If there is such a proof, would the work of Russell in the period 1901 to 1906 have any connection with Einstein's 1905 paper? Russell's obscure mathematics flew in the face of logic; and not too dissimilarly, Einstein's obscure mathematics survived being contradicted by empirical observations. And the powers of the world would presumably have liked to keep the truth about high energy physics secret. Still, it is for that reason impossible to know either way.
If God deliberately created this universe in such a way that there was such a proof, then we might expect the universe to be full of people taking themselves to be living in God's family. And if Einstein was wrong about the light-speed-limit, then that might make a difference to us.
Wednesday, September 05, 2018
What Do Philosophers Do?
(A) The overwhelming majority of professional mathematicians are not going to be wrong about what numbers are.
(B) The overwhelming majority of mathematicians assume, in their professional work, that numbers are axiomatic sets.
(C) Numbers are not axiomatic sets.
The conjunction of (A), (B) and (C) would be a contradiction, were the mathematicians of (B) not just assuming that numbers are axiomatic sets for the purposes of proving theorems from axioms, as I suspect they do. But many analytic philosophers deny (C), because of that apparent contradiction. Such philosophers also ask questions like: “Do numbers (or sets) exist? If they do, where are they? If they don’t, then what does ‘2’ refer to?”
The implication is that since numbers (or sets) are abstract objects, hence if they do exist then they exist in some Platonic realm of abstract objects, raising the question: “How is it that we can access that realm, in order to know such properties of numbers as arithmetic?” To see how stupid such questions are, one only has to ask such questions as: “Does value exist; and if so, where is it?” Clearly some things have value, but it makes no sense to ask where it is (or what colour it is); such questions hardly further the analytical task of describing accurately what value is.
A question similar to the one about numbers might be: “Do shapes exist?” Shapes are instantiated in, and abstracted from, shaped things, clearly; and similarly, whole numbers are instantiated in, and abstracted from, numbers of things. That is basically what John Stuart Mill said (in passing); it is only common sense, although his observation was jumped on by a founder of analytic philosopher, Gottlob Frege (incorrectly).
Sunday, March 11, 2018
Definitive Selections?
When we think of some things, and various combinations of them, it seems clear that all those combinatorial possibilities are there already, awaiting our consideration. And yet I am asking you to imagine that when a Creator, some such brilliant mind, considers some things, all those possibilities are blurred together (although none so blurry that it cannot be picked out); or am I?
I am suggesting that for selections of selections of ... of selections, from some original collections, each possible selection from those will be a particular possibility only as it is actually selected by our Creator, independently of whom no collections of things would exist, were there such a Creator (as there provably is). The possible selections that make S(N) bigger than N (to use the terminology in my Cantorian diagonal argument) are those endless sequences of ‘I’s and ‘O’s that are pseudorandom; to make them, infinitely many selections have to be made, each one of which involves some arbitrarily large finite number of selections. They might be made instantaneously by our Creator, of course; and if so, then typical selections from S(N) could be made arbitrarily quickly.
What about S(S(N)), which contains more things than infinite space contains points? Well, a Creator might be able to do all of that instantaneously. And similarly for selections from U, and UU, and maybe UUU; but still, you see how our Creator would have to do much more, and much, much more, and so on and so forth, without end. It is therefore quite plausible that for selection-collections that it would take me far more than mere trillions of pages to describe, our Creator would be unable or unwilling (and thence unable) to make all such selections instantaneously. After all, it is logically impossible for all possible selections to be made instantaneously. To will an incremental development of such abstract mathematics, as a necessary aspect of the creation of any things, might be regarded as a price worth paying for some such creations. And it is also quite plausible that were the Creator unable to do something (even as a consequence of such a choice) then that thing really would be impossible, given that the very possibility of it derives from that Creator.
Solid things are solid; but mathematical properties related rather abstractly to their individuality can be works in progress; why not? Modern mathematics has a weirder story to tell of such matters! It is relatively straightforward to think of Creation as dependent upon a Creator who transcends even its mathematics. So, it may not be too odd to think of a Creator creating number by definitively adding units: 1, 2, 3 and so forth; is that any weirder than a Creator creating something ex nihilo? Number is paradoxical, so that the ultimate totalities of numbers are indefinitely extensible, and so numbers just do pop into existence, somehow; and what more reasonable way than by their being constructed by a Creator? What would be very weird indeed would be their popping into existence all by themselves, what with them being essentially structural possibilities rather than concrete things. It makes some sense to think of us creating them, as we think about the world around us, but there is something very objective about numbers of things. And again, if it makes sense for us to do it, then how can it be too odd to think of a Creator doing it, in a Platonistic way?
There will be better ways to think of definitive selection, I am sure; but, it is the case that such weaselly words are the norm nowadays. For example, how can simple brute matter (just atoms, in molecules of atoms, each just some electrons around a nucleus) have feelings, such sensitive feelings as we have? How is that possible? Am I asking for a description of a possible mechanism? Perhaps; but a common enough answer is: Well, it must be possible, because we have such feelings, in this physical universe; although I don't know how sensitive we humans really are, looking at our world! Such answers are accepted by many scientific people, as they "work" on possible mechanisms!
Monday, March 05, 2018
Apparently Timeless Possibilities
become more numerous over time, e.g. as follows:
You were always possible,
but had you never existed,
then that possibility would have been
the possibility of someone just like you.
It could not have been
the possibility of you in particular
were you not there to refer to.
Looking back now,
we can see that there was always
that possibility, of you in particular
as well as the more general possibility,
even before you came into being.
Now, Presentism is logically possible,
and if Presentism is true then there may
originally have been no such distinction,
even though you were always possible.
Under Presentism it could have been
that you might not have existed.
The distinction could therefore have
arisen when you came into being.
It is therefore logically possible
for apparently timeless possibilities
to emerge as distinct possibilities
from more general possibilities.
The Signature of God
I think belief in God reasonable only if it is based on considerations available to all humans: not if it is claimed on the basis of a special message to oneself or to the group that one belongs.Anthony Kenny ("Knowledge, Belief, and Faith," Philosophy 82, 381-97)
So what better signature of the creator of homo sapiens than an elementary logical proof that there is a God? In my last post, I described the argument that given some things, cardinally more selections from them are possible.
That post ended with a brief description of how that means that paradox arises: we naturally assume that each of the possible selections that such endlessly reiterated selection-collections and infinite unions would or could ever show there to be is already a possibility, that it is already there, as a possible selection; it would follow that they were all there already, that they are collectively some impossible collection of all those possible selections.
Logic dictates that we have made some mistake; and this version of Cantor's paradox arises because we are considering combinatorially possible selections: that is why the sub-collections that define those selections were able to become so paradoxically numerous, why the paradoxical contradiction did not just show that there are not, after all, so many extra things, over and above the original things.
My resolution begins by observing that apparently timeless possibilities could, possibly, become more numerous over time; it begins that way because if possible selections are always becoming more numerous, then we would never have all of them. A Constructive Creator could, possibly, make the definitive selections; and if that is the only logical possibility, then that is what has been shown.
Note that serious mathematicians have taken Constructive mathematics seriously, and when constructed by a transcendent Creator the mathematics would be much more Platonic, and much more Millian. Consider, for an analogy, how God's commands could, just possibly, define ethics. And note that such creative possibilities are not that different to the Creating of mere things ex nihilo, if you think about it: how is such Creation even possible? For us, the laws of physics present immutable limits to what can be done; for a God, such laws are, metaphorically, a brushstroke.
We live in a world of things, and numbers of things; and for us, numbers appear timeless. But logic does seem to say that such numbers are impossible. When we first think of the origin of things, we might think of things that could have been there forever, like numbers. But logic seems to say that there was originally stuff, not things; perhaps mental stuff, perhaps a God that is not exactly one thing. There would have been some possibility of things, and more arithmetic the more that God thought about that possibility.
I should add a note about what sort of God is being shown to exist. The proof does not show that God could not have created a four-dimensional world in a Creative act above and beyond that temporal dimension. So this God might be what we call "timeless," and might know all about the future; or not. And either way, this God could always have known all of our textbook mathematics, if only because that is essentially axiomatic.
Monday, February 12, 2018
Doppelgangers
Indeed, you cannot completely rule out the possibility that you are such a doppelganger, because you would have exactly the same memories, exactly the same sense of being yourself. There would be absolutely no empirical difference; the only difference would be semantic: reference intended to be reference to you would fail to be such reference, were it to d-you, for example (and given the falsity of Functionalism, and so forth). And of course, knowledge would be lost, e.g. if I saw d-you at a bus-stop then I would not know that you were waiting for a bus. But of course, I would know that you were waiting for a bus if I saw you at a bus-stop (and you were waiting for a bus). There is no loss of knowledge caused by not ruling out the logical possibility of d-you. We simply assume that such swapping does not happen.
Note that we do not just think it unlikely (and similarly, we do not just think it unlikely that we are brains in vats, or being fooled by demons, and so on and so forth). We do not know for sure that there are no such doppelgangers, and we do not even know for sure that there are unlikely to be any (we can have no evidence for such unlikeliness). But clearly, we are assuming that there are no such things (and nothing else of that rather wide-ranging kind). That is just an obvious empirical fact about our beliefs. (We might not notice it, because being fooled by a demon would be like being a brain in an evil scientist’s vat, and a brain in a vat is like someone having a very long vivid dream; and maybe it is only highly unlikely that you are in a coma right now.)
Thursday, February 08, 2018
Truth in Dreams
Wednesday, February 07, 2018
Lots of Misprints
taking the book, turning to the page, and pointing to three separate places on it, saying 'There's one misprint here, another here, and another here'Maddy 2017: 164 (Moore 1939: 147) Although of course, while that proves that there are three misprints, it does not prove that there are three misprints. And while you might agree with Moore that those were misprints, that would not amount to a proof that they were. Moore, you will recall, does not have to show that there are two hands, nor even that there are two hands, he has to show the externality (so to speak) of such things as hands, given skeptical doubts, which is more like having to prove not just assume, that it is indeed a bad thing to have lots of misprints. And of course, why would we have to prove such a thing! Ask yourself what is meant by "external world" to see for yourself how it exists by definition (and note how one gestures as one does so). And yet, it is precisely that "proof" that is challenged by skeptical doubts (as the above-linked-to review of Maddy 2017 observes).
Tuesday, February 06, 2018
What do Philosophers do?
Here's a thought though:
Thursday, January 18, 2018
50 meanings for "know"
Sunday, January 14, 2018
Much Knowledge is Epistemic Luck
And similarly, we cannot really rule out that we are Brains In Vats: all of our evidence is compatible with our brains having been harvested by aliens (in a real world where such aliens are common) and put into high-tech vats that simulate worldly experiences. While we are unlikely to have been harvested recently (as recently noted (although note that we cannot rule out as unlikely a world where are are frequently, but not too frequently, re-vatted)) it is not unlikely (by the standards of the apparent world) that there are such aliens (what is strange is that we see no aliens).
But of course, we can and do simply assume that there are not such aliens, that we are not currently asleep in our beds and dreaming, that all of our particles are not always being switched with identical particles, and so forth. It is upon such foundations that our knowledge of the external world is built. And of course, we are not BIVs, we are not dreaming, and so on; or at least, I do assume not. And so we do have knowledge of the external world. But, because those are assumptions, such knowledge is epistemic luck.
Thursday, January 11, 2018
What Do Philosophers Do?
for example, could be justified ( you may be using them now,
to operate a phone or a keyboard), but you can hardly rule out
the following scenario, according to which you have no hands:
Your brain was recently harvested by aliens and you are now in a vat
experiencing a detailed simulation; your memories have been altered,
but for you "hand" still refers to things outside the vat. And out there,
those aliens have turned the real world into one enormous brain-farm.
You cannot rule that out,
but you can know that it is unlikely
that your brain was only recently harvested
and so you can, of course, know that you have hands.
Friday, February 28, 2014
Who's Afraid of Veridical Wool?
Cantor and Russell
Cantor’s paradox concerned the set of all the other sets because the set of all the sets would have had to contain itself as one of its own members, and we do not normally think of collections like that. But as Russell thought about Cantor’s counter-intuitive mathematics, he considered the collection of all the sets that do not belong to themselves: If that collection was a set, then it would belong to itself if, and only if, it did not belong to itself. That is basically Russell’s paradox. Like Cantor’s, it is not obviously paradoxical – it just means that there is no such set – but Russell thought of sets as the definite extensions of definite predicates, and predicate versions of his paradox are more obviously paradoxical. E.g. consider W.V.O. Quine’s version: ‘Is not true of itself’ is true of itself if, and only if, it is not true of itself. That is paradoxical because we naturally assume that ‘is not true of itself’ will either be true of itself, or else it will not. But if predicate expressions can be about as true as not of themselves, then it would follow from the meaning of ‘is not true of itself’ that insofar as ‘is not true of itself’ is true of itself it is not true of itself, and that insofar as it is not true of itself it is not the case that it is not true of itself. And it would follow that ‘is not true of itself’ is about as true as not of itself.
Monday, November 18, 2013
I think, so I'm iffy
......To make such an effort is to force the future away from a state that it would otherwise be in, of course. And for me to think of that state as already unreal would undermine my motivation to make such an effort. And of course, for me to make no such effort would be for me to care little for the quality of my thoughts, which would be irrational.
......That was a précis of my comments on a Prussian post, themselves inspired by Nicholas Denyer's 1981 defence of arguments like "I deliberate, so my will is free."